Sociology
Sociology is the study of human behavior. Sociology refers to social behavior, society, patterns of social relationships, social interaction, and culture that surround everyday life. It is a social science that uses various methods of empirical investigation and critical analysis to develop a body of knowledge about social order and social change. Sociology can also be defined as the general science of society. While some sociologists conduct research that may be applied directly to social policy and welfare, others focus primarily on refining the theoretical understanding of social processes. Subject matter can range from micro-level analyses of society (i.e., of individual interaction and agency) to macro-level analyses (i.e., of systems and the social structure). Traditional focuses of sociology include social stratification, social class, social mobility, religion, secularization, law, sexuality, gender, and deviance. As all spheres of human activity are affected by the interplay between social structure and individual agency, sociology has gradually expanded its focus to other subjects and institutions, such as health and the institution of medicine; economy; military; punishment and systems of control; the Internet; education; social capital; and the role of social activity in the development of scientific knowledge.
The range of social scientific
methods has also expanded, as social researchers draw upon a variety
of qualitative and quantitative techniques.
The linguistic and cultural turns of the mid-20th century,
especially, have led to increasingly interpretative, hermeneutic,
and philosophic approaches towards the analysis of society.
Conversely, the turn of the 21st century has seen the rise of
new analytically, mathematically, and computationally rigorous
techniques, such as agent-based modeling and social network
analysis.
Origins
Sociological reasoning
predates the foundation of the discipline itself. Social analysis has
origins in the common stock of Western knowledge and philosophy,
having been carried out from as far back as the time of Old comic
poetry which features social and political
criticism, and ancient Greek philosophers Socrates, Plato,
and Aristotle, if not earlier. For instance, the origin of the survey (i.e.,
the collection of information from a sample of individuals) can be traced back
to at least the Doomsday Book in 1086, while ancient
philosophers such as Confucius wrote about the importance of social
roles.
There is evidence of early
sociology in medieval Arabic writings as well. Some sources consider Ibn
Khaldun, a 14th-century Arab-Islamic
scholar from Tunisia, to have been the father of sociology
although there isn't reference to his work in the work of major founders of
modern sociology. Khaldun's Muqaddimah was perhaps the
first work to advance social-scientific reasoning on social
cohesion and social conflict.
Comte
"Sociology" was later defined independently by French philosopher of science Auguste Comte in 1838 as a new way of looking at society. Comte had earlier used the term "social physics," but it had been subsequently appropriated by others, most notably the Belgian statistician Adolphe Quetelet. Comte endeavoured to unify history, psychology, and economics through the scientific understanding of the social realm. Writing shortly after the malaise of the French Revolution, he proposed that social ills could be remedied through sociological positivism, an epistemological approach outlined in the Course in Positive Philosophy (1830–1842), later included in A General View of Positivism (1848). Comte believed a positivist stage would mark the final era, after conjectural theological and metaphysical phases, in the progression of human understanding. In observing the circular dependence of theory and observation in science, and having classified the sciences, Comte may be regarded as the first philosopher of science in the modern sense of the term.
Comte
gave a powerful impetus to the development of sociology, an impetus which bore
fruit in the later decades of the nineteenth century. To say this is certainly
not to claim that French sociologists such as Durkheim were devoted
disciples of the high priest of positivism. But by insisting on the
irreducibility of each of his basic sciences to the particular science of sciences
which it presupposed in the hierarchy and by emphasizing the nature of
sociology as the scientific study of social phenomena Comte put sociology on
the map. To be sure, [its] beginnings can be traced back well
beyond Montesquieu, for example, and to Condorcet, not to speak
of Saint-Simon, Comte's immediate predecessor. But Comte's clear
recognition of sociology as a particular science, with a character of its own,
justified Durkheim in regarding him as the father or founder of this science,
in spite of the fact that Durkheim did not accept the idea of the three states
and criticized Comte's approach to sociology.
Marx
Both Comte and Karl
Marx set out to develop scientifically justified systems in the wake of
European industrialization and secularization, informed by
various key movements in the philosophies of history and science.
Marx rejected Comtean positivism but in attempting to develop a
"science of society" nevertheless came to be recognized as a founder
of sociology as the word gained wider meaning. For Isaiah
Berlin (1967), even though Marx did not consider himself to be a
sociologist, he may be regarded as the "true father" of modern
sociology, "in so far as anyone can claim the title."
To have given clear and
unified answers in familiar empirical terms to those theoretical questions
which most occupied men's minds at the time, and to have deduced from them
clear practical directives without creating obviously artificial links between
the two, was the principal achievement of Marx's theory. The sociological treatment
of historical and moral problems, which Comte and after
him, Spencer and Taine, had discussed and mapped, became a
precise and concrete study only when the attack of militant Marxism made its
conclusions a burning issue, and so made the search for evidence more zealous
and the attention to method more intense.
Spencer
Herbert
Spencer (1820–1903) was one of the most popular and influential
19th-century sociologists. It is estimated that he sold one million books in
his lifetime, far more than any other sociologist at the time. So strong was
his influence that many other 19th-century thinkers, including Émile
Durkheim, defined their ideas in relation to his. Durkheim's Division
of Labour in Society is to a large extent an
extended debate with Spencer from whose sociology, many commentators now agree,
Durkheim borrowed extensively. Also a notable biologist, Spencer
coined the term survival of the fittest. While Marxian ideas
defined one strand of sociology, Spencer was a critic of socialism as well as strong
advocate for a laissez-faire style of government. His ideas were
closely observed by conservative political circles, especially in
the United States and England.
Positivism
and antipositivism
The
overarching methodological principle of positivism is to
conduct sociology in broadly the same manner as natural science. An
emphasis on empiricism and the scientific method is sought
to provide a tested foundation for sociological research based on the
assumption that the only authentic knowledge is scientific knowledge, and that
such knowledge can only arrive by positive affirmation through scientific
methodology.
The term has long since ceased
to carry this meaning; there are no fewer than twelve distinct epistemologies
that are referred to as positivism. Many of these approaches do not
self-identify as "positivist", some because they themselves arose in
opposition to older forms of positivism, and some because the label has over
time become a pejorative term by being mistakenly linked with a
theoretical empiricism. The extent of antipositivist criticism
has also diverged, with many rejecting the scientific method and others only
seeking to amend it to reflect 20th-century developments in the philosophy of
science. However, positivism (broadly understood as a scientific approach to
the study of society) remains dominant in contemporary sociology, especially in
the United States.
Loïc Wacquant distinguishes
three major strains of positivism: Durkheimian, Logical,
and Instrumental. None
of these are the same as that set forth by Comte, who was unique in advocating
such a rigid (and perhaps optimistic) version. While Émile Durkheim rejected
much of the detail of Comte's philosophy, he retained and refined its method.
Durkheim maintained that the social sciences are a logical continuation of the
natural ones into the realm of human activity, and insisted that they should
retain the same objectivity, rationalism, and approach to causality. He
developed the notion of objective sui generis "social
facts" to serve as unique empirical objects for the science of sociology
to study. The variety of positivism that remains dominant today is termed instrumental
positivism. This approach eschews epistemological and metaphysical concerns
(such as the nature of social facts) in favour of methodological
clarity, replicability, reliability and validity. This
positivism is more or less synonymous with quantitative research, and so
only resembles older positivism in practice. Since it carries no explicit
philosophical commitment, its practitioners may not belong to any particular
school of thought. Modern sociology of this type is often credited to Paul
Lazarsfeld, who pioneered large-scale survey studies and developed
statistical techniques for analysing them. This approach lends itself to
what Robert K. Merton called middle-range theory: abstract
statements that generalize from segregated hypotheses and empirical
regularities rather than starting with an abstract idea of a social whole.
Anti-positivism
Reactions against social empiricism
began when German philosopher Hegel voiced opposition to both
empiricism, which he rejected as uncritical, and determinism, which he viewed
as overly mechanistic. Karl Marx's methodology borrowed from Hegelian
dialecticism but also a rejection of positivism in favour of critical
analysis, seeking to supplement the empirical acquisition of "facts"
with the elimination of illusions. He maintained that appearances need to be
critiqued rather than simply documented. Early hermeneuticians such
as Wilhelm Dilthey pioneered the distinction between natural and
social science ('Geisteswissenschaft').
Various neo-Kantian philosophers, phenomenologists and human
scientists further theorized how the analysis of the social
world differs to that of the natural world due to the
irreducibly complex aspects of human society, culture, and being.
In the Italian context of
development of social sciences and of sociology in particular, there are
oppositions to the first foundation of the discipline, sustained by speculative
philosophy in accordance with the antiscientific tendencies matured by critique
of positivism and evolutionism, so a tradition Progressist struggles to
establish itself.
At the turn of the 20th
century the first generation of German sociologists formally introduced
methodological anti-positivism, proposing that research should concentrate
on human cultural norms, values, symbols, and social processes
viewed from a resolutely subjective perspective. Max Weber argued that
sociology may be loosely described as a science as it is able to
identify causal relationships of human "social
action"—especially among "ideal types", or hypothetical
simplifications of complex social phenomena. As a non-positivist, however,
Weber sought relationships that are not as "historical, invariant, or
generalisable" as those pursued by natural scientists. Fellow German
sociologist, Ferdinand Tönnies, theorised on two
crucial abstract concepts with his work on "gemeinschaft and gesellschaft"
(lit. 'community' and 'society'). Tönnies marked a sharp line
between the realm of concepts and the reality of social action: the first must
be treated axiomatically and in a deductive way ("pure sociology"),
whereas the second empirically and inductively ("applied sociology").
[Sociology is] ... the science whose object is
to interpret the meaning of social action and thereby give
a causal explanation of the way in which the action
proceeds and the effects which it produces. By 'action' in
this definition is meant the human behaviour when and to the extent that the
agent or agents see it as subjectively meaningful ... the
meaning to which we refer may be either (a) the meaning actually intended
either by an individual agent on a particular historical occasion or by a
number of agents on an approximate average in a given set of cases, or (b) the
meaning attributed to the agent or agents, as types, in a pure type constructed
in the abstract. In neither case is the 'meaning' to be thought of as somehow
objectively 'correct' or 'true' by some metaphysical criterion. This is the
difference between the empirical sciences of action, such as sociology and
history, and any kind of prior discipline, such as
jurisprudence, logic, ethics, or aesthetics whose aim is to extract from their
subject-matter 'correct' or 'valid' meaning.
Both Weber and Georg
Simmel pioneered the "Verstehen" (or 'interpretative')
method in social science; a systematic process by which an outside observer
attempts to relate to a particular cultural group, or indigenous people, on
their own terms and from their own point of view. Through the work of
Simmel, in particular, sociology acquired a possible character beyond
positivist data-collection or grand, deterministic systems of structural law.
Relatively isolated from the sociological academy throughout his lifetime,
Simmel presented idiosyncratic analyses of modernity more reminiscent of
the phenomenological and existential writers than of Comte
or Durkheim, paying particular concern to the forms of, and possibilities for,
social individuality. His sociology engaged in a neo-Kantian inquiry into
the limits of perception, asking 'What is society?' in a direct allusion to
Kant's question 'What is nature?'
The deepest problems of modern
life flow from the attempt of the individual to maintain the independence and
individuality of his existence against the sovereign powers of society, against
the weight of the historical heritage and the external culture and technique of
life. The antagonism represents the most modern form of the conflict which
primitive man must carry on with nature for his own bodily existence. The
eighteenth century may have called for liberation from all the ties which grew
up historically in politics, in religion, in morality and in economics in order
to permit the original natural virtue of man, which is equal in everyone, to
develop without inhibition; the nineteenth century may have sought to promote,
in addition to man's freedom, his individuality (which is connected with the
division of labor) and his achievements which make him unique and indispensable
but which at the same time make him so much the more dependent on the
complementary activity of others; Nietssche may have seen the relentless
struggle of the individual as the prerequisite for his full development, while
socialism found the same thing in the suppression of all competition – but
in each of these the same fundamental motive was at work, namely the resistance
of the individual to being leveled, swallowed up in the social-technological
mechanism.
No comments:
Post a Comment